What you don’t know CAN hurt you: Epistemic Injustice and Conceptually Impoverished Health Promotion
avatar

I want to consider a particular kind of wrong within medicine and health promotion: epistemic injustice and its harms. My case study is obesity conceived of as a public health concern. However, the analytic framework I deploy may prove useful in ethically assessing many health promotion campaigns.

This image combines two images, side by side. One is a fat young girl looking unhappy, with her arms crossed. The text reads "WARNING: it's hard to be a littler girl if you're not. Stop childhood obesity. strong4life.com" The other image shows a fat boy with an unhappy expression and his hands in his pockets, slouching. The text reads "WARNING: fat prevention begins at home. And the buffet line. Stop childhood obesity. strong4life.com"

Note the message on the left that being a normal girl is incompatible with being a fat girl, or a happy one. On the right, there is a pretty explicit indication of individual personal responsibility (“Fat prevention begins at home. And the buffet line.”).

Individuals—both doctors and patients—are often provided with an impoverished set of conceptual tools for making sense of health and health behaviors, a set of tools that can lead to inappropriate individualization of responsibility and to unproductive attitudes towards health and which behaviors are health promoting.  This is the case with obesity.  Public health campaigns and clinical care of obese persons rely on a family of simplistic reductions.

The first reduction is that body size correlates reliably with health: witness the use of Body Mass Index (BMI) to diagnose obesity, and the medicalization of obesity as not just a risk condition but a disease in its own right. In June of 2013, the American Medical Association’s House of Delegates endorsed the notion of obesity as a disease defined primarily by BMI, joining the World Health Organization (WHO), U.S. Food and Drug Administration (FDA), and the U.S. National Institutes of Health (NIH).  In the International Classification of Diseases (ICD-10), cases of obesity which are not caused by metabolic disorders or pharmaceuticals are classified as “hyperalimentation”: overeating.

This brings us to the second reduction in the conceptual toolkit available to doctors and patients: that obesity is caused by over-eating, and weight gain/loss is a simple calories-in-calories-out equation.  This etiology shows up in public health campaigns, in the clinical recommendation that patients eat better and get more exercise, and in the widespread use of dieting in Western culture.

As I have argued in my 2015 IJFAB article, by focusing us on body size as a measure of health, and on calories-in-calories-out as both an explanation and a treatment for obesity, these two reductions create a third: the locus of responsibility for obesity falls upon the individual rather than on systemic features contributing to ill health.  Consider, in the U.S., then-First Lady Michelle Obama’s “Let’s Move!” campaign which took little or no account of factors in the built environment which make it dangerous to exercise in many neighborhoods due to crime or traffic and which place residential areas often quite distant from workplaces and necessary errands, thus disincentivizing foot travel. “Let’s Move!” explicitly aimed to “solve” the epidemic of childhood obesity within a generation. While it included discussion of healthy foods in schools—an environmental factor—it also explicitly addressed “healthy moms” and “healthy families” thereby placing responsibility for health disproportionately onto women and individual family units, much as the framing of obesity places individual responsibility onto fat adults generally.

A third form of reductivism is well-documented in physician diagnosis of fat patients’ ills as originating in fatness, such that fat patients with joint pain will be met with directions to lose weight rather than, say, a consideration of rheumatoid arthritis or a recommendation for physical therapy. This contributes to misdiagnosis and undertreatment.

By providing clinicians, patients, and the general public with reductive frameworks, public health campaigns foster several forms of epistemic injustice. The first of these is hermeneutic injustice. As described by Miranda Fricker, this occurs when a knower is harmed because she lacks the toolset to make sense of her lived experience.  It may be that, while both doctors and patients can be impoverished, power relations mean that only patients truly suffer injustice from insufficient toolsets.  This is especially the case with dominant frameworks about obesity which foster a calories-in-calories-out reductivism, leading to widespread failure of weight loss regimes, and to damaging assertions of individual responsibility.

Interwoven with this is unjustified skepticism about patient testimony that contradicts simplistic conceptual frameworks. So entrenched are these reductions that physicians who see that patients have not lost weight often presume they have been non-compliant, and that fat patients who claim to eat well and exercise must be lying. Indeed, adjectives American doctors most associate with fatness include “noncompliant” and “lazy.” Fricker calls this form of epistemic injustice testimonial injustice, in which a knower is harmed because her testimony is unjustly discounted; the knower experiences a credibility deficit in relation to her audience based in part on irrelevant traits such as body size.

A fourth and final form of epistemic injustice occurs when fat patients stop going to the doctor because of testimonial and hermeneutic injustice. This is what Kristie Dotson calls testimonial smothering: a knower stays silent because she believes her testimony will be dismissed. When doctors attribute patient ills to obesity and discount patient testimony, physicians teach patients that seeking medical treatment will not in fact produce health.

The conceptual frameworks provided by health promotion are often simplistic, as with that for obesity. Kukla has shown some of these same features with breastfeeding campaigns. Epistemic injustice, a wrong in itself, occurs and in turn causes other forms of harm including patient withdrawal from medical care and devastating internalization of individualized responsibility.  More nuanced frameworks can prevent such harms and in doing so can better accomplish the promotion of health.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Allen Buchanan. 2002. “Social Moral Epistemology.” Social Philosophy and Policy 19(2): 126-152.

——-. 2004. “Political Liberalism and Social Epistemology.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 32(2):95-130.

Kamagra an impotence medicine it has become one of the preferred methods of selling goods and services across the world: Ability to organize and track the shipment from time to time a) Online status and billing b) Online dispatch of invoice c) Auto reminder for payments d) Information systems report e) Online alerts for critical information continue reading description purchase cheap levitra via texts or emails, etc. The discount web chemists give is actually their profit that they share generic tadalafil from india with the end users. It is also known to relieve pain and provide overall comfort to mind and body. viagra tablets uk pdxcommercial.com Erectile dysfunction is generic levitra 5mg one such disorder that has shattered dreams of millions of men’s. American Medical News. 2013. “Confronting bias against obese patients.” American Medical News. Retrieved June 6, 2016 from http://www.amednews.com/article/20130902/profession/130909988/4/.

Bachman. 2015. “Weight Loss or Not, Exercise Yields Benefits.” The Wall Street Journal.

Cardiovascular Research Foundation. 2008. “Signs Of Heart Disease Are Attributed To Stress More Frequently In Women Than Men.” ScienceDaily. Retrieved June 6, 2016 from www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2008/10/081012121314.htm.

Kristie Dotson. “Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing.” Hypatia 26(2): 236-257. 2011.

GD Foster, TA Wadden, AP Makris, D Davidson, RS Sanderson, DB Allison, and A Kessler. 2003. “Primary care physicians’ attitudes about obesity and its treatment.” Obesity Research 11(10): 1168-77.

Miranda Fricker. 2007. Epistemic Injustice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Jeffery, Epstein, Wilson, Drewnoski, Stunkard, and Wing. 2000. “Long-term maintenance of weight loss: current status.” Health Psychology 19:5-16.

Kassirer and Angell. “Editorial: Losing Weight—An Ill-fated New Year’s Resolution.” New England Journal of Medicine 338(16): 1156.

Kramer, Jeffery, Forster, and Snell. 1989. “Long-term follow-up of behavioral treatment for obesity: patterns of weight regain among men and women.” International Journal of Obesity 13:123-36.

Rebecca Kukla. 2006. “Ethics and Ideology in Breastfeeding Campaigns.” Hypatia 21(1): 157-181.

Mann, Tomiyama, Westling, Lew, Samuels, and Chatman.  2007. “Medicare’s search for effective obesity treatments: diets are not the answer.” American Psychologist  3:220-33.

Kathryn Montgomery. 2006. How Doctors Think: Clinical Judgment and the Practice of Medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Alison Reiheld. 2015. “With All Due Caution: Global Anti-Obesity Campaigns and the Individualization of Responsibility.” International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 8(2): 226-249.

Abigail Saguy. 2013a. “If Obesity Is a Disease, Why are So Many Obese People Healthy?” TIME.

Abigail Saguy. 2013b. “How ‘size profiling’ harms overweight patients.” The Washington Post.

Share Button

Comments

What you don’t know CAN hurt you: Epistemic Injustice and Conceptually Impoverished Health Promotion — 1 Comment

  1. Great post! Testimonial injustice (and then smothering) seems importantly connected to holding someone accountable, and, thereby, respecting them. If someone’s testimony isn’t acknowledged/accepted, it means they aren’t respected as capable of providing accurate/trustworthy narratives, rendering them not full moral agents. Couldn’t agree with you more about these issues in health promotion.

Leave a Reply to Kate MacKay Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.